Skip to content

Latest commit

 

History

History
871 lines (668 loc) · 35 KB

subtyping.md

File metadata and controls

871 lines (668 loc) · 35 KB

Dart 2.0 Static and Runtime Subtyping

[email protected]

Status: This document is now background material. For normative text, please consult the language specification.

This is intended to define the core of the Dart 2.0 static and runtime subtyping relation.

Types

The syntactic set of types used in this draft are a slight simplification of full Dart types.

The meta-variables X, Y, and Z range over type variables.

The meta-variables T, S, U, and V range over types.

The meta-variable C ranges over classes.

The meta-variable B ranges over types used as bounds for type variables.

As a general rule, indices up to k are used for type parameters and type arguments, n for required value parameters, and m for all value parameters.

The set of types under consideration are as follows:

  • Type variables X
  • Promoted type variables X & T Note: static only
  • Object
  • dynamic
  • void
  • Null
  • Never
  • Function
  • Record
  • Future<T>
  • FutureOr<T>
  • T?
  • T*
  • Interface types C, C<T0, ..., Tk>
  • Function types
    • U Function<X0 extends B0, ...., Xk extends Bk>(T0 x0, ...., Tn xn, [Tn+1 xn+1, ..., Tm xm])
    • U Function<X0 extends B0, ...., Xk extends Bk>(T0 x0, ...., Tn xn, {Tn+1 xn+1, ..., Tm xm})
  • Record types
    • (T0, ...., Tn, {Tn+1 xn+1, ..., Tm xm})

We leave the set of interface types unspecified, but assume a class hierarchy which provides a mapping from interfaces types T to the set of direct super-interfaces of T induced by the superclass declaration, implemented interfaces, and mixins of the class of T. Among other well-formedness constraints, the edges induced by this mapping must form a directed acyclic graph rooted at Object.

The types dynamic and void are both referred to as top types, and are considered equivalent as types (including when they appear as sub-components of other types). They exist as distinct names only to support distinct errors and warnings (or absence thereof).

The type Object is the super type of all concrete types except Null.

The type X & T represents the result of a type promotion operation on a variable. In certain circumstances (defined elsewhere) a variable x of type X that is tested against the type T (e.g. x is T) will have its type replaced with the more specific type X & T, indicating that while it is known to have type X, it is also known to have the more specific type T. Promoted type variables only occur statically (never at runtime).

The type Null represents the type of the null constant.

The type Never represents the uninhabited bottom type.

The type T? represents the nullable version of the type T, interpreted semantically as the union type T | Null.

The type T* represents a legacy type which may be interpreted as nullable or non-nullable as appropriate.

Given the current promotion semantics the following properties are also true:

  • If X has bound B then for any type X & T, T <: B will be true.
  • Promoted type variable types will only appear as top level types: that is, they can never appear as sub-components of other types, in bounds, or as part of other promoted type variables.

For convenience, we generally write function types with all named parameters in an unspecified canonical order, and similarly for the named fields of record types. In all cases unless otherwise specifically called out, order of named parameters and fields is semantically irrelevant: any two types with the same named parameters (named fields, respectively) are considered the same type.

Notation

We use S[T0/Y0, ..., Tk/Yk] for the result of performing a simultaneous capture-avoiding substitution of types T0, ..., Tk for the type variables Y0, ..., Yk in the type S.

Type equality

We say that a type T0 is equal to another type T1 (written T0 === T1) if T0 <: T1 and T1 <: T0.

Algorithmic subtyping

By convention the following rules are intended to be applied in top down order, with exactly one rule syntactically applying. That is, rules are written in the form:

Syntactic criteria.
  - Additional condition 1
  - Additional or alternative condition 2

and it is the case that if a subtyping query matches the syntactic criteria for a rule (but not the syntactic criteria for any rule preceeding it), then the subtyping query holds iff the listed additional conditions hold. Specifically, once a rule has matched syntactically, the answer to the subtyping query is entirely given by that rule: it is never necessary to try subsequent rules.

This makes the rules algorithmic, because they correspond in an obvious manner to an algorithm with an acceptable time complexity, and it makes them syntax directed because the overall structure of the algorithm corresponds to specific syntactic shapes. We will use the word algorithmic to refer to this property.

The runtime subtyping rules can be derived by eliminating all clauses dealing with promoted type variables.

Rules

Note the convention described in the section above

We say that a type T0 is a subtype of a type T1 (written T0 <: T1) when:

  • Reflexivity: if T0 and T1 are the same type then T0 <: T1

    • Note that this check is necessary as the base case for primitive types, and type variables but not for composite types. In particular, algorithmically a structural equality check is admissible, but not required here. Pragmatically, non-constant time identity checks here are counter-productive
  • Right Top: if T1 is a top type (i.e. dynamic, or void, or Object?) then T0 <: T1

  • Left Top: if T0 is dynamic or void then T0 <: T1 if Object? <: T1

  • Left Bottom: if T0 is Never then T0 <: T1

  • Right Object: if T1 is Object then:

    • if T0 is an unpromoted type variable with bound B then T0 <: T1 iff B <: Object
    • if T0 is a promoted type variable X & S then T0 <: T1 iff S <: Object
    • if T0 is FutureOr<S> for some S, then T0 <: T1 iff S <: Object.
    • if T0 is S* for any S, then T0 <: T1 iff S <: T1
    • if T0 is Null, dynamic, void, or S? for any S, then the subtyping does not hold (per above, the result of the subtyping query is false).
    • Otherwise T0 <: T1 is true.
  • Left Null: if T0 is Null then:

    • if T1 is a type variable (promoted or not) the query is false
    • If T1 is FutureOr<S> for some S, then the query is true iff Null <: S.
    • If T1 is Null, S? or S* for some S, then the query is true.
    • Otherwise, the query is false
  • Left Legacy: if T0 is S0* then:

    • T0 <: T1 iff S0 <: T1.
  • Right Legacy: if T1 is S1* then:

    • T0 <: T1 iff T0 <: S1?.
  • Left FutureOr: if T0 is FutureOr<S0> then:

    • T0 <: T1 iff Future<S0> <: T1 and S0 <: T1
  • Left Nullable: if T0 is S0? then:

    • T0 <: T1 iff S0 <: T1 and Null <: T1
  • Type Variable Reflexivity 1: if T0 is a type variable X0 or a promoted type variables X0 & S0 and T1 is X0 then:

    • T0 <: T1
    • Note that this rule is admissible, and can be safely elided if desired
  • Type Variable Reflexivity 2: if T0 is a type variable X0 or a promoted type variables X0 & S0 and T1 is X0 & S1 then:

    • T0 <: T1 iff T0 <: S1.
    • Note that this rule is admissible, and can be safely elided if desired
  • Right Promoted Variable: if T1 is a promoted type variable X1 & S1 then:

    • T0 <: T1 iff T0 <: X1 and T0 <: S1
  • Right FutureOr: if T1 is FutureOr<S1> then:

    • T0 <: T1 iff any of the following hold:
      • either T0 <: Future<S1>
      • or T0 <: S1
      • or T0 is X0 and X0 has bound S0 and S0 <: T1
      • or T0 is X0 & S0 and S0 <: T1
  • Right Nullable: if T1 is S1? then:

    • T0 <: T1 iff any of the following hold:
      • either T0 <: S1
      • or T0 <: Null
      • or T0 is X0 and X0 has bound S0 and S0 <: T1
      • or T0 is X0 & S0 and S0 <: T1
  • Left Promoted Variable: T0 is a promoted type variable X0 & S0

    • and S0 <: T1
  • Left Type Variable Bound: T0 is a type variable X0 with bound B0

    • and B0 <: T1
  • Function Type/Function: T0 is a function type and T1 is Function

  • Record Type/Record: T0 is a record type and T1 is Record

  • Interface Compositionality: T0 is an interface type C0<S0, ..., Sk> and T1 is C0<U0, ..., Uk>

    • and each Si <: Ui
  • Super-Interface: T0 is an interface type with super-interfaces S0,...Sn

    • and Si <: T1 for some i
  • Positional Function Types: T0 is U0 Function<X0 extends B00, ..., Xk extends B0k>(V0 x0, ..., Vn xn, [Vn+1 xn+1, ..., Vm xm])

    • and T1 is U1 Function<Y0 extends B10, ..., Yk extends B1k>(S0 y0, ..., Sp yp, [Sp+1 yp+1, ..., Sq yq])
    • and p >= n
    • and m >= q
    • and Si[Z0/Y0, ..., Zk/Yk] <: Vi[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk] for i in 0...q
    • and U0[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk] <: U1[Z0/Y0, ..., Zk/Yk]
    • and B0i[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk] === B1i[Z0/Y0, ..., Zk/Yk] for i in 0...k
    • where the Zi are fresh type variables with bounds B0i[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk]
  • Named Function Types: T0 is U0 Function<X0 extends B00, ..., Xk extends B0k>(V0 x0, ..., Vn xn, {r0n+1 Vn+1 xn+1, ..., r0m Vm xm}) where r0j is empty or required for j in n+1...m

    • and T1 is U1 Function<Y0 extends B10, ..., Yk extends B1k>(S0 y0, ..., Sn yn, {r1n+1 Sn+1 yn+1, ..., r1q Sq yq}) where r1j is empty or required for j in n+1...q
    • and {yn+1, ... , yq} subsetof {xn+1, ... , xm}
    • and Si[Z0/Y0, ..., Zk/Yk] <: Vi[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk] for i in 0...n
    • and Si[Z0/Y0, ..., Zk/Yk] <: Tj[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk] for i in n+1...q, yj = xi
    • and for each j such that r0j is required, then there exists an i in n+1...q such that xj = yi, and r1i is required
    • and U0[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk] <: U1[Z0/Y0, ..., Zk/Yk]
    • and B0i[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk] === B1i[Z0/Y0, ..., Zk/Yk] for i in 0...k
    • where the Zi are fresh type variables with bounds B0i[Z0/X0, ..., Zk/Xk]
  • Record Types: T0 is (V0, ..., Vn, {Vn+1 dn+1, ..., Vm dm})

    • and T1 is (S0, ..., Sn, {Sn+1 dn+1, ..., Sm dm})
    • and Vi <: Si for i in 0...m

Note: the requirement that Zi are fresh is as usual strictly a requirement that the choice of common variable names avoid capture. It is valid to choose the Xi or the Yi for Zi so long as capture is avoided

Derivation of algorithmic rules

This section sketches out the derivation of the algorithmic rules from the interpretation of FutureOr<T> and T? as union types, and promoted type bounds as intersection types, based on standard rules for such types that do not satisfy the requirements for being algorithmic.

Non-algorithmic rules

The non-algorithmic rules that we derive from first principles of union and intersection types are as follows, where: S0 | S1 stands in for either FutureOr<S> (in which case S0 is Future<S> and S1 is S) or S? (in which case S0 is S, and S1 is Null); and S0 & S1 stands in for X & S (in which case S0 is X and S1 is S).

Left union introduction:

  • S0 | S1 <: T if S0 <: T and S1 <: T

Right union introduction:

  • S <: T0 | T1 if S <: T0 or S <: T1

Left intersection introduction:

  • S0 & S1 <: T if S0 <: T or S1 <: T

Right intersection introduction:

  • S <: T0 & T1 if S <: T0 and S <: T1

Axiom for Object:

Right nullable Object:

  • T <: Object?

The declarative legacy subtyping rules are derived from the possible completions of the legacy type to a non-legacy type.

Right legacy introduction:

  • T* <: S if T <: S or T? <: S

Left legacy introduction:

  • T <: S* if T <: S or T <: S?

The only remaining non-algorithmic rule is the variable bounds rule:

Variable bounds:

  • X <: T if X extends B and B <: T

All other rules are algorithmic.

Preliminaries

Lemma 1: If there is any derivation of S0 | S1 <: T (that is, either FutureOr<S> <: T or S? <: T), then there is a derivation ending in a use of left union introduction.

Proof. By induction on derivations. Consider a derivation of S0 | S1 <: T.

If the last rule applied is:

  • Top type rules (including nullable object) are trivial.

  • Object, Null, Never, Function and interface rules can't apply.

  • Left union introduction rule is immediate.

  • Right union introduction. Then T is of the form T0 | T1 and either

    • we have a sub-derivation of S0 | S1 <: T0
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in left union introduction, so by inversion we have:
        • a derivation of S0 <: T0 , and so by right union introduction we have S0 <: T0 | T1
        • a derivation of S1 <: T0 , and so by right union introduction we have S1 <: T0 | T1
      • by left union introduction, we have S0 | S1 <: T0 | T1
      • QED
    • we have a sub-derivation of S0 | S1 <: T1
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in left union introduction, so by inversion we have:
        • a derivation of S0 <: T1 , and so by right union introduction we have S0 <: T0 | T1
        • a derivation of S1 <: T1 , and so by right union introduction we have S1 <: T0 | T1
      • by left union introduction, we have S0 | S1 <: T0 | T1
      • QED
  • Right intersection introduction. Then T is of the form T0 & T1, and

    • we have sub-derivations S0 | S1 <: T0 and S0 | S1 <: T1
    • By induction, we can get derivations of the above ending in left union introduction, so by inversion we have derivations of:
      • S0 <: T0, S1 <: T0, S0 <: T1, S1 <: T1
        • so we have derivations of S0 <: T0, S0 <: T1, so by right intersection introduction we have
          • S0 <: T0 & T1
        • so we have derivations of S1 <: T0, S1 <: T1, so by right intersection introduction we have
          • S1 <: T0 & T1
    • so by left union introduction, we have a derivation of S0 | S1 <: T0 & T1
  • Left legacy introduction cannot apply

  • Right legacy introduction. Then T is of the form T0*, and

    • we have one of the following cases for the immediate sub-derivation:
      • if we have S0 | S1 <: T, then by induction, there is a derivation ending in a use of left union introduction, so by inversion we have:
        • a derivation of S0 <: T, so by right legacy introduction we have S0 <: T*
        • a derivation of S1 <: T, so by right legacy introduction we have S1 <: T*
        • so by left union introduction we have S0 | S1 <: T*
      • if we have S0 | S1 <: T?, then by induction, there is a derivation ending in a use of left union introduction, so by inversion we have:
        • a derivation of S0 <: T?, so by right legacy introduction we have S0 <: T*
        • a derivation of S1 <: T?, so by right legacy introduction we have S1 <: T*
        • so by left union introduction we have S0 | S1 <: T*
  • QED

Note: The reverse is not true. Counter-example:

Given arbitrary B <: A, suppose we wish to show that (X extends FutureOr<B>) <: FutureOr<A>. If we apply right union introduction first, we must show either:

  • X <: Future<A>
  • only variable bounds rule applies, so we must show
    • FutureOr<B> <: Future<A>
    • Only left union introduction applies, so we must show both of:
      • Future<B> <: Future<A> (yes)
      • B <: Future<A> (no)
  • X <: A
  • only variable bounds rule applies, so we must show that
    • FutureOr<B> <: A
    • Only left union introduction applies, so we must show both of:
      • Future<B> <: Future<A> (no)
      • B <: Future<A> (yes)

On the other hand, the derivation via first applying the variable bounds rule is trivial.

Note though that we can also not simply always apply the variable bounds rule first. Counter-example:

Given X extends Object, it is trivial to derive X <: FutureOr<X> via the right union introduction rule. But applying the variable bounds rule doesn't work.

Lemma 2: If there is any derivation of S <: T0 & T1, then there is derivation ending in a use of right intersection introduction.

Proof. By induction on derivations. Consider a derivation D of S <: T0 & T1.

If last rule applied in D is:

  • Never and non-nullable Null rules are trivial.

  • Top types cannot apply.

  • Function and interface type rules can't apply.

  • Right intersection introduction then we're done.

  • Left intersection introduction. Then S is of the form S0 & S1, and either

    • we have a sub-derivation of S0 <: T0 & T1
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in right intersection introduction, so by inversion we have:
        • a derivation of S0 <: T0 , and so by left intersection introduction we have S0 & S1 <: T0
        • a derivation of S0 <: T1 , and so by left intersection introduction we have S0 & S1 <: T1
      • by right intersection introduction, we have S0 & S1 <: T0 & T1
      • QED
    • we have a sub-derivation of S1 <: T0 & T1
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in right intersection introduction, so by inversion we have:
        • a derivation of S1 <: T0, and so by left intersection introduction we have S0 & S1 <: T0
        • a derivation of S1 <: T1, and so by left intersection introduction we have S0 & S1 <: T1
    • by right intersection introduction, we have S0 & S1 <: T0 & T1
    • QED
  • Left union introduction. Then S is of the form S0 | S1, and

    • we have sub-derivations S0 <: T0 & T1 and S1 <: T0 & T1
    • By induction, we can get derivations of the above ending in right intersection introduction, so by inversion we have derivations of:
      • S0 <: T0, S1 <: T0, S0 <: T1, S1 <: T1
        • so we have derivations of S0 <: T0, S1 <: T0, so by left union introduction we have
          • S0 | S1 <: T0
        • so we have derivations of S0 <: T1, S1 <: T1, so by left union introduction we have
          • S0 | S1 <: T1
    • so by right intersection introduction, we have a derivation of S0 | S1 <: T0 & T1
  • Right union introduction can't apply.

  • Left legacy introduction. Then S is of the form S0*, and either

    • we have a sub-derivation of S0 <: T0 & T1
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in right intersection introduction, so by inversion we have:
        • a derivation of S0 <: T0 , and so by left intersection introduction we have S0* <: T0
        • a derivation of S0 <: T1 , and so by left intersection introduction we have S0* <: T1
      • by right intersection introduction, we have S0* <: T0 & T1
      • QED
    • we have a sub-derivation of S0? <: T0 & T1
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in right intersection introduction, so by inversion we have:
        • a derivation of S0? <: T0 , and so by left intersection introduction we have S0* <: T0
        • a derivation of S0? <: T1 , and so by left intersection introduction we have S0* <: T1
      • by right intersection introduction, we have S0* <: T0 & T1
      • QED
  • Right legacy introduction can't apply.

  • Variable bounds rule. Then S is of the form X where X extends B and we have a derivation of B <: T0 & T1.

    • By induction, we have derivation ending in right intersection introduction, so by inversion we have:
      • a derivation of B <: T0, and so by the variable bounds rule we have X <: T0.
      • a derivation of B <: T1, and so by the variable bounds rule we have X <: T1.
    • So by right intersection introduction, we have X <: T0 & T1.
  • QED

Observation 1:

  • If T <: S is derivable, then T <: S? is derivable by right union introduction
  • If T? <: S is derivable, then T <: S is derivable since by lemma 1 there is a derivation ending in left union introduction, and hence there is a sub-derivation of T <: S.

This observation justifies the following simpler derived rules for the legacy types:

Left legacy introduction (derived):

  • T* <: S if T <: S

Right legacy introduction (derived):

  • T <: S* if T <: S?

Lemma 3: If there is any derivation of S* <: T, then there is a derivation ending in a use of left legacy introduction.

Proof. By induction on derivations. Consider a derivation of S* <: T.

If the last rule applied is:

  • Top type rules are trivial.

  • Object is trivial

  • Null, Never, Function and interface rules can't apply.

  • Left union introduction rule doesn't apply.

  • Right union introduction. Then T is of the form T0 | T1 and either

    • we have a sub-derivation of S* <: T0
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in left legacy introduction
        • so by inversion we have a derivation of S <: T0
        • so by right union introduction we have S <: T0 | T1
      • so by left legacy introduction, we have S* <: T0 | T1
      • QED
    • we have a sub-derivation of S* <: T1
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in left legacy introduction
        • so by inversion we have a derivation of S <: T1
        • so by right union introduction we have S <: T0 | T1
      • so by left legacy introduction, we have S* <: T0 | T1
      • QED
  • Left intersection introduction cannot apply.

  • Right intersection introduction. Then T is of the form T0 & T1, and

    • we have sub-derivations S* <: T0 and S* <: T1
    • By induction, we can get derivations of the above ending in left legacy introduction.
    • so by inversion we have derivations of S <: T0 and S <: T1
    • so by right intersection introduction we have a derivation of S <: T0 & T1
    • so by left legacy introduction we have a derivation of S* <: T0 & T1
  • Left legacy introduction is immediate.

  • Right legacy introduction. Then T is of the form T0*, and

    • by inversion we have a derivation of S* <: T0?
    • by induction we have a derivation of this ending in left legacy introduction, and hence by inversion we have a derivation of S <: T0?
    • by right legacy introduction we have S <: T0*
    • by left legacy introduction we have S* <: T0*
  • QED

Lemma 4: If there is any derivation of S <: T*, then there is derivation ending in a use of right legacy introduction.

Proof. By induction on derivations. Consider a derivation D of S <: T*.

If last rule applied in D is:

  • Never rule is trivial.

  • Top, Function and interface type rules can't apply.

  • Left intersection introduction. Then S is of the form S0 & S1, and either

    • we have a sub-derivation of S0 <: T*
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in right legacy introduction, so by inversion we have a derivation of S0 <: T?
      • so by left intersection introduction we have S0 & S1 <: T?
      • so we have S0 & S1 <: T* by right legacy introduction.
    • we have a sub-derivation of S1 <: T*
      • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in right legacy introduction, so by inversion we have a derivation of S1 <: T?
      • so by left intersection introduction we have S0 & S1 <: T?
      • so we have S0 & S1 <: T* by right legacy introduction.
  • Right intersection introduction doesn't apply

  • Left union introduction. Then S is of the form S0 | S1, and

    • we have sub-derivations S0 <: T* and S1 <: T*
    • By induction, we can get derivations of the above ending in right legacy introduction, so by inversion we have derivations of S0 <: T?, S1 <: T?
    • so by left union introduction we have S0 | S1 <: T?
    • so by right legacy introduction we have S0 | S1 <: T*
  • Right union introduction can't apply.

  • Left legacy introduction. Then S is of the form S0*, and we have a sub-derivation of S0 <: T*

    • by induction we therefore have a derivation ending in right legacy introduction
    • so by inversion we have a derivation of S0 <: T0?
    • so by left legacy introduction we have S0* <: T0?
    • so by right legacy introduction, we have S0* <: T0*
    • QED
  • Right legacy introduction is immediate.

  • Variable bounds rule. Then S is of the form X where X extends B and we have a derivation of B <: T*.

    • By induction, we have a derivation ending in right legacy introduction, so by inversion we have a derivation of B <: T?
    • so by the variables bounds rule, we have X <: T?
    • so by right legacy introduction we have X <: T*
  • QED

Note: It is easy to see that A <: B implies FutureOr<A> <: FutureOr<B>, but the converse does not hold. Counter-example (due to @fishythefish):

Consider a class A which implements Future<Future<A>> (such a class is definable in Dart). Let B be Future<A>. Note that A <: B is not derivable, since to show this requires that Future<Future<A>> <: Future<A> (super-interface), which requires that Future<A> <: A, which does not hold.

But we can show that FutureOr<A> <: FutureOr<B> as follows:

  • It suffices to show that A <: FutureOr<B> and Future<A> <: FutureOr<B>
    • To show that A <: FutureOr<B>, it suffices to show that A <: Future<B>, which holds by the super-interface rule plus identity.
    • To show that Future<A> <: FutureOr<B> it suffices to show that Future<A> <: B which holds by identity.

Lemma 10: Transitivity of subtyping without the legacy type rules is admissible. Given derivations of A <: B and B <: C which does not use any of the legacy rules, then there is a derivation of A <: C which also does not use any of the legacy rules.

Proof sketch: The proof should go through by induction on sizes of derivations, cases on pairs of rules used. For any pair of rules used, we can construct a new derivation of the desired result using only smaller derivations.

Observation 2: Given X with bound S, we have the property that for all instances of X & T, T <: S will be true, and hence S <: M => T <: M.

Observation 3: The following are not derivable for any T:

  • T? <: Object, since by lemma 1 we must have Null <: Object
  • Null <: X for any unpromoted type variable X
    • there are no typing rules which apply
  • Null <: X & T for any promoted type variable X
    • the only rule that applies is left intersection introduction, which in turn requires that Null <: X.

Observation 4: The following are derivable for any T:

  • Null <: T?, since it suffices to show that Null <: Null
  • Null <: T*, since it suffices to show that Null <: T?

Algorithmic rules

Consider T0 <: T1.

True top on the right

If T1 is dynamic or void or Object? the query is true.

True bottom on the left

If T0 is Never the query is true.

Object

If T1 is Object:

  • if T0 is an unpromoted type variable with bound B, the query is true iff B <: Object is true.
    • The only rule that can apply is the variable bounds rule.
  • if T0 is a promoted type variable X & S with bound B then the query is true iff S <: Object is true
    • The only rule that applies is left intersection introduction
    • Hence we must show X <: Object or S <: Object. For the former, the only rule which applies is the variable bounds rule, so it suffices to show that B <: Object and S <: Object. But by observation 2, we have that S <: B, so it suffices to show that S <: Object.
  • If T0 is FutureOr<S> for some S, then the query is true iff S <: Object.
    • By lemma 1, it suffices to show that Future<S> <: Object and S <: Object, and the former holds immediately.
  • If T0 is Null, dynamic, void, or S? for any S, the query is false.
    • By Observation 3 above
  • If T0 is S* for any S, the query is true iff S <: Object by lemma 3.
  • Otherwise the query is true.
    • In this case, T0 must be Object, a function type, or interface type.

Null

If T0 is Null

  • if T1 is a type variable (promoted or not) the query is false
    • By observation 3
  • If T1 is FutureOr<S> for some S, then the query is true iff Null <: S.
    • The only rule that applies is right union introduction which requires either Null <: Future<S> or Null <: S. The former is never true so it suffices to check the latter.
  • If T1 is Null, S? or S* for some S, then the query is true.
    • By Observaton 4 above
  • Otherwise, the query is false
    • In this case, T1 is Object, a function type, or an interface type.

Legacy on the left

If T0 is S* for some S, the query is true iff S <: T1 is true

  • By lemma 3 above, and the derived version of the legacy left introduction rule

Legacy on the right

If T1 is S* for some S, the query is true iff T0 <: S? is true

  • By lemma 4 above, and the derived version of the legacy right introduction rule.

Union on the left

By lemma 1, if T0 is of the form FutureOr<S0> and there is any derivation of T0 <: T1, then there is a derivation ending with a use of left union introduction so we have the rule:

  • T0 is FutureOr<S0>
    • and Future<S0> <: T1
    • and S0 <: T1

By lemma 1, if T0 is of the form S0? and there is any derivation of T0 <: T1, then there is a derivation ending with a use of left union introduction so we have the rule:

  • T0 is S0?
    • and S0 <: T1
    • and Null <: T1

Identical type variables

If T0 and T1 are both the same unpromoted type variable, then subtyping holds by reflexivity. If T0 is a promoted type variable X0 & S0, and T0 is X0 then it suffices to show that X0 <: X0 or S0 <: X0, and the former holds immediately. This justifies the rule:

  • T0 is a type variable X0 or a promoted type variables X0 & S0 and T1 is X0.

If T0 is X0 or X0 & S0 and T1 is X0 & S1, then by lemma 1 it suffices to show that X0 & S0 <: X0 and X0 & S0 <: S1. The first holds immediately by reflexivity on the type variable, so it is sufficient to check T0 <: S1.

  • T0 is a type variable X0 or a promoted type variables X0 & S0 and T1 is X0 & S1
    • and T0 <: S1.

Note that neither of these type variable rules are required to make the rules algorithmic: they are merely useful special cases of the next rule.

Intersection on the right

By lemma 2, if T1 is of the form X1 & S1 and there is any derivation of T0 <: T1, then there is a derivation ending with a use of right intersection introduction, hence the rule:

  • T1 is a promoted type variable X1 & S1
    • and T0 <: X1
    • and T0 <: S1

Union on the right

Suppose T1 is FutureOr<S1>. The rules above have eliminated the possibility that T0 is of the form FutureOr<S0>, S0*, or S0?. The only rules that could possibly apply then are right union introduction, left intersection introduction, or the variable bounds rules. Combining these yields the following preliminary disjunctive rule:

  • T1 is FutureOr<S1> and
    • either T0 <: Future<S1>
    • or T0 <: S1
    • or T0 is X0 and X0 has bound S0 and S0 <: T1
    • or T0 is X0 & S0 and X0 <: T1 and S0 <: T1

The last disjunctive clause can be further simplified to

  • or T0 is X0 & S0 and S0 <: T1

since the premise X0 <: FutureOr<S1> can only be derived either using the variable bounds rule or right union introduction. For the variable bounds rule, the premise B0 <: T1 is redundant with S0 <: T1 by observation 2. For right union introduction, X0 <: S1 is redundant with T0 <: S1, since if X0 <: S1 is derivable, then T0 <: S1 is derivable by left intersection introduction; and X0 <: Future<S1> is redundant with T0 <: Future<S1>, since if the former is derivable, then the latter is also derivable by left intersection introduction. So we have the final rule:

  • T1 is FutureOr<S1> and
    • either T0 <: Future<S1>
    • or T0 <: S1
    • or T0 is X0 and X0 has bound S0 and S0 <: T1
    • or T0 is X0 & S0 and S0 <: T1

Suppose T1 is S1?. The rules above have eliminated the possibility that T0 is of the form FutureOr<S0>, S0*, or S0?. The only rules that could possibly apply then are right union introduction, left intersection introduction, or the variable bounds rules. Combining these yields the following preliminary disjunctive rule:

  • T1 is S1? and
    • either T0 <: S1
    • or T0 <: Null
    • or T0 is X0 and X0 has bound S0 and S0 <: T1
    • or T0 is X0 & S0 and X0 <: T1 and S0 <: T1

The last disjunctive clause can be further simplified to

  • or T0 is X0 & S0 and S0 <: T1

since the premise X0 <: S1? can only be derived either using the variable bounds rule or right union introduction. For the variable bounds rule, the premise B0 <: T1 is redundant with S0 <: T1 by observation 2. For right union introduction, X0 <: S1 is redundant with T0 <: S1, since if X0 <: S1 is derivable, then T0 <: S1 is derivable by left intersection introduction; and X0 <: Null is redundant with T0 <: Null, since if the former is derivable, then the latter is also derivable by left intersection introduction. So we have the final rule:

  • T1 is S1? and
    • either T0 <: S1
    • or T0 <: Null
    • or T0 is X0 and X0 has bound S0 and S0 <: T1
    • or T0 is X0 & S0 and S0 <: T1

Intersection on the left

At this point, we've eliminated the possibility that T1 is FutureOr<S1>, the possibility that T1 is S1?, the possibility that T1 is S1*, the possibility that T1 is X1 & S1, the possibility that T1 is any variant of X0, and the possibility that T1 is any of the top types, or Object. The only remaining possibilities for T1 are function types or non-top interfaces types.

Suppose T0 is X0 & S0. Given that we have eliminated all of the structural types as possibilities for T1, the only remaining rule that applies is left intersection introduction, and so it suffices to check that X0 <: T1 and S0 <: T1. But given the remaining possible forms for T1, the only rule that can apply to X0 <: T1 is the variable bounds rule, which by observation 2 is redundant with the second premise, and so we have the rule:

T0 is a promoted type variable X0 & S0

  • and S0 <: T1

Type variable on the left

Suppose T0 is X0. Given that we have eliminated all of the structural types as possibilities for T1, the only rule that applies is the variable bounds rule:

T0 is a type variable X0 with bound B0

  • and B0 <: T1

This eliminates all of the non-algorithmic rules: the remainder are strictly syntax driven.

Changelog

  • July 12th, 2019: Replaced conjecture on FutureOr subtyping with counter-example.
  • Jan 29th, 2019: Fixed legacy rules.
  • Dec 19th, 2018: Added subtyping for nullable types and transitional legacy types.